At
the heart of William Deresiewicz’s ill-advised, reactionary attack on Michael
Chwe’s 2013 book Jane Austen Game
Theorist is the assertion that Chwe’s game theory approach adds no value to
our collective understanding of Jane Austen’s novels, which we didn’t already
garner from “normal” literary criticism. I will in this post give significant additional
evidence to rebut Deresiewicz’s assertion, and also to extend Michael’s
theorizing into a new realm, simply by paying close attention to JA’s wordplay while
keeping Chwe’s arguments in mind.
In one
section of Chapter 6 of his book, Chwe discusses the theme of “choice” in JA’s six
novels (treated as a whole). I will now give you quotes from those half dozen
pages, stripped of examples, to give you a glimpse of his organized, insightful
approach to this topic:
CHWE:
“For Austen, choice is a central concern, even obsession. The single most important
choice is a woman’s choice of whether and whom to marry, and Austen’s heroines
adamantly defend this choice against any presumption otherwise.…Thoughtful men
are aware that women can make choices…. Idiotic men are not aware…Being able to
make a choice is almost always a good thing for Austen; it is “a great deal
better to chuse than to be chosen” (E, p. 15).
There
is power in being able to make a choice…. Even when it seems better to not have
to make a choice, Austen shows that another choice can make things better
still. Correspondingly, for Austen, people who cannot make choices deserve
ridicule or worse. …For Austen, choices bind. You can’t have it both ways. Once
you make a choice, you cannot pretend you did not make it. …Austen hates
encumbered choices. …being empowered and unencumbered improves both choice and
result. Austen explains that to make a choice thoughtfully, you must understand
the counterfactual of what would have happened had you chosen otherwise (in
economics, this is the concept of “opportunity cost”). …Understanding the
proper counterfactual, imagining all aspects of what would have happened had
you chosen differently, is not always easy.” END QUOTE FROM CHWE’S BOOK
Any
group of knowledgeable Janeites who read that section of Chwe’s book, including
the examples he provides, along with other examples which might occur to them,
could spend intellectually fruitful hours discussing the novels through this
lens of the theme of choice. Chwe is correct---choice IS an obsession of JA’s,
and it is a wide portal leading directly into the core of JA’s complex moralism—the
infinite variety of how people make difficult choices.
And
so the example Chwe mentioned in his rebuttal to Deresiewicz (Mrs. Weston
analyzing Jane Fairfax’s choices in game theory-like terms, which Emma had not
considered) was perfectly chosen—it illustrates that an author who put such
words in a character’s mouth must, of necessity, have first thought in those
terms herself.
And it’s
doesn’t require arcane scientific knowledge in order to think intelligently
about the overarching theme of choice in JA’s novels. It’s just that, generally
speaking, as Chwe also pointed out, it simply doesn’t occur to most readers to
actually decide to take this approach and then follow through on it! As I’ve
asserted countless times, so much of the most interesting stuff in JA’s fiction
is accessible only after it first occurs to us to take a fresh perspective on
texts we’ve read dozens of times before.
As I
wrote in my last post about Michael’s book, JA is NOT the kind of heavy-handed
writer who provides appendices, waving her hands frantically in order to get
readers to engage with her deeper subtextual themes. Rather, JA provides
countless light winks, hints and nods, small textual smiles which alert the
sensitive reader to pay closer attention to a particular theme.
And I
have found that one key aspect of the Jane Austen Code is the satirical nature of
so much of her winking and hinting, and her pervasive use of wordplay in that
process.
The
perfect textual example of this is the one I brought forward yesterday, Mr.
Bennet’s witty catechism of Lizzy’s UNHAPPY ALTERNATIVE in her choice as to whether to accept Mr.
Collins’s proposal:
"Come
here, child," cried her father as she appeared. "I have sent for you
on an affair of importance. I understand that Mr. Collins has made you an offer
of marriage. Is it true?" Elizabeth replied that it was. "Very well—and
this offer of marriage you have REFUSED?"
"I
have, sir."
"Very
well. We now come to the point. Your mother insists upon your ACCEPTING it. Is it not so, Mrs. Bennet?"
"Yes,
or I will never see her again."
"An
UNHAPPY ALTERNATIVE is before you, Elizabeth.
From this day you must be a stranger to one of your parents. Your mother will
never see you again if you do not marry Mr. Collins, and I will never see you
again if you do."
Elizabeth
could not but SMILE at such a conclusion of such a beginning, but Mrs. Bennet,
who had persuaded herself that her husband regarded the affair as she wished,
was excessively disappointed.
"What
do you mean, Mr. Bennet, in talking this way? You promised me to insist upon
her marrying him."
… Mr.
Collins, meanwhile, was meditating in solitude on what had passed. He thought
too well of himself to comprehend on what motives his cousin could REFUSE him…
Mr.
Bennet parodically assumes the role of a pedantic schoolmaster teaching logic
to a student, and brilliantly reduces Lizzy’s choice to its essential
absurdity. And one of the Top Five comic moments in all of literature was
thereby created.
But
here’s my meta-point. It was only after I read Chwe’s rebuttal to Deresiewicz,
in which Chwe included the example of Mrs. Weston alerting Emma to Jane
Fairfax’s choices, that it occurred to me to see Mr. Bennet’s famous bon mot in
the fresh light of a parody of logical choice-making, or what we today call
game theory.
And,
once the seed was planted to look at P&P from this fresh perspective, I soon
noticed, also for the first time, that Mr. Bennet’s parody of a logical theorem
was only the BEGINNING of JA’s further parodic treatment of this theme in
P&P!
There
are (at least) two more passages later in P&P which are part and parcel of
this motif, textual interconnections which have been hiding in plain sight in this most
popular and reread of novels for 2 centuries.
Mr.
Bennet’s logical exercise occurs near the end of Chapter 20 of P&P. Now look at the interaction of Lizzy and Jane
less than a chapter later, in Chapter 21:
"But,
my dear sister, can I be happy, even supposing the best, in ACCEPTING a man
whose sisters and friends are all wishing him to marry elsewhere?"
"You
must DECIDE for yourself," said Elizabeth; "and if, upon MATURE
DELIBERATION, you find that the misery of disobliging his two sisters is MORE
THAN EQUIVALENT to the happiness of being his wife, I advise you by all means
to REFUSE him."
"How
can you talk so?" said Jane, FAINTLY SMILING. "You must know that though
I should be exceedingly grieved at their disapprobation, I could not
hesitate."
"I
did not think you would; and that being the case, I cannot consider your
situation with much compassion."
"But
if he returns no more this winter, my CHOICE will never be required.
A
thousand things may arise in six months!"
The
idea of his returning no more Elizabeth treated with the utmost contempt.”
Isn’t
it obvious that Lizzy so enjoyed her father’s witty parody of cost benefit analysis
of the Collins proposal, that she translated it at her first opportunity to her
sister’s hypothetical response to Bingley’s hypothetical proposal? Elizabeth “could not but smile” at her father’s
joke at her mother’s expense, and Jane, in turn “faintly smil[es]” at Lizzy’s
admirable emulation of Dear Old Dad. The rhetorical apple has indeed not fallen
far from the paternal tree.
And there’s
yet a further iteration of this motif, as JA milks the joke for all it’s worth,
but, as always, with the lightest, most
subtle touch, and the deepest concealed meaning—there’s an echo of the proposal
refusal parody five chapters later, when Charlotte “proposes” to Elizabeth that
Lizzy visit her in Kent:
"I
am not likely to leave Kent for some time. Promise me, therefore, to come to
Hunsford."
ELIZABETH
COULD NOT REFUSE , though she foresaw little pleasure in the visit.
"My
father and Maria are coming to me in March," added Charlotte, "and I hope
you will consent to be of the party. Indeed, Eliza, you will be as welcome as
either of them."
I put
”proposal” in quotes, because I have suggested many times that Charlotte is a
closeted lesbian who has secretly and
unrequitedly loved Elizabeth for years. Therefore her request that Lizzy
promise to visit in March has the veiled connotation, from Charlotte’s point of
view, of a romantic proposal—so how lovely that, unlike her negative responses
to both Collins and (in the first go-round, at least) Darcy, “Elizabeth could
NOT refuse” Charlotte’s proposal! It does suggest, with exquisite subtlety,
that Elizabeth does, however unconsciously, reciprocate Charlotte’s secret
love.
And,
again, I saw all of this only because that one short section of Chwe’s book got
me thinking about choice in JA’s novels. I believe this is a vindication of the
right questions posed by Chwe in his book, which provoked me to find these
answers.
Whereas,
I’ve read entire books about Jane Austen by respected, conventional literary
critics which did not in any way inspire me to see something new and
interesting in JA’s writing.
So Chwe’s
book is, again, a breath of very fresh air in the world of Austen scholarship, and
I for one will continue to take deep breaths and dance up a rhetorical storm, despite
Deresiewicz’s very Mr. Wooohouse-like abhorrence of literary critical dancing with
open windows!
Cheers,
ARNIE
@JaneAustenCode
on Twitter
No comments:
Post a Comment